Beliefs | Children's Ministry | Directions | Favorite Links | Home | Photo | Salvation | Resources |
Greek History and Thought
by Steven Kreis,
PhD
Homer and the Greek
Renaissance, 900-600BC
Rage – Goddess, sing the rage of Peleus' son Achilles,
murderous, doomed, that cost the Achaeans countless losses, hurling down to the
House of Death so many sturdy souls, great fighters' souls, but made their
bodies carrion, feasts for the dogs and birds, and the will of Zeus was moving
toward its end. Begin, Muse, when the first two broke and clashed, Agamemnon
lord of men and brilliant Achilles.
What god drove them to fight with such fury? Apollo the
son of Zeus and Leto. Incensed at the king he swept a fatal plague through the
army – men were dying and all because Agamemnon spurned Apollo's priest. Yes,
Chryses approached the Achaeans' fast ships to win his daughter back, bringing a
priceless ransom and bearing high in hand, wound on a golden staff, the wreaths
of the god, the distant deadly Archer. He begged the whole Achaean army but most
of all the two supreme commanders, Atreus' two sons, "Agamemnon, Menelaus – all
Argives geared for war! May the gods who hold the halls of Olympus give you
Priam's city to plunder, then safe passage home. Just set my daughter free, my
dear one . . . here, accept these gifts, this ransom. Honor the god who strikes
from worlds away – the son of Zeus, Apollo!"
And all ranks of Achaeans cried out their assent:
"Respect the priest, accept the shining ransom!" But it brought no joy to the
heart of Agamemnon. The king dismissed the priest with a brutal order ringing in
his ears: "Never again, old man, let me catch sight of you by the hollow ships!
Not loitering now, not slinking back tomorrow. The staff and the wreaths of god
will never save you then. The girl – I won't give up the girl. Long before that,
old age will overtake her in my house, in Argos, far from her fatherland,
slaving back and forth at the loom, forced to share my bed!
Now go, don't tempt my wrath – and you may depart
alive."
Throughout the past 2500 years of western history there has
been a tendency on the part of one age after another to go back in time to find
something of itself in the past. The quest for collective identity has often
taken scholars, artists, intellectuals, philosophers, scientists and others back
to that historical point in time in which it all began. For us moderns of the
past 500 years, that tendency is strong and it is no accident that we have often
found our identity in the world of Classical Greece. There is something about
the word "classical" that is indeed appealing. We speak about classical music, a
classic film or even classic Coke. By calling something classic we mean that it
stands the test of time, or that it is number one, or that in all times and all
places it is somehow good.
The ancient Greeks seemed to have placed western society as
well as the western intellectual tradition on a footing or groundwork that
remains to this day. We take this foundation for granted, for the simple reason
that the Greeks of the classical age seemed to have discovered so many things
which today matter a great deal. So, although our voyage into the ancient past
has begun with the Ancient Near East we now find ourselves on the Attic
peninsula, in the heart of the ancient Mediterranean world.
Greek history itself can be broken down into many distinct
eras – historians break down the past for the simple reason that these eras
provide focal points for study and dialogue. In general, Greek history can be
broken down in the following way:
Archaic Greece 3000-1600 B.C.
Mycenaen Greece 1600-1200 B.C.
Dark Ages 1200-800 B.C.
Greek Renaissance 800-600 B.C.
Classical or Hellenic Greece 600-323 B.C.
Hellenistic Greece 323-31 B.C.
This section deals with a rather broad expanse of
historical time, beginning with Archaic Greece and ending with the creation of
Athenian direct democracy during the Greek Renaissance.
Before we begin, we have to ask ourselves a few fundamental
questions. If we are about to discuss the Greek Renaissance, then we must first
ask ourselves what is meant by the expression "Renaissance." As we all know, the
word "renaissance" simply means rebirth – a new birth, something perhaps
entirely new, a watershed, a turning point, a point at which things changed. For
the historian looking at the western intellectual tradition it means primarily a
revival of the arts and letters and is usually associated with that period of
European history between 1300 and 1500 when scholars and artists in northern
Italian city states, Holland, France and England witnessed the rebirth of a
golden age.
The golden age was, of course, classical Greece. But the
term "renaissance," which Renaissance humanists created to describe their own
period of light, is a value-charged expression. What this means is that calling
something a renaissance implies a value judgment. On the one hand it implies
that something before the Renaissance must have died. And Renaissance scholars
gave that something a name – they called it the media aetis – a middle age.
Middle of what? Well obviously, middle between the Renaissance and the classical
world. The Middle Ages have always gotten a bad rap – why do you think they are
usually referred to as the Dark Ages? Simple. Renaissance artists were so
conceited that they called their own age "like a golden age" – anything that
came immediately before it must have been somehow bad or dark.
Of course, there has been more than one Renaissance in the
past. For instance, we have the Greek Renaissance. And then there's the
Carolingian Renaissance of the 8th and 9th centuries and the 12th century
Renaissance.
The first important society in the Greek world developed on
the large island of Crete, just south of the Aegean Sea. The people of Crete
were not Greek but probably came from western Asia Minor well before 3000 B.C.
In 1900, the English archeologist, Arthur Evans (1851-1941), excavated Knossos,
the greatest city of ancient Crete. There he discovered the remains of a
magnificent palace which he named the Palace of Minos, the mythical king of
Crete (and so, Cretan civilization is also known as Minoan). The palace
bureaucrats of Crete wrote in a script called Linear A and although their
language has not been fully deciphered, it is assumed that they may have been a
member of the Indo-European family of languages, which includes Greek and Latin.
With an estimated population of 250,000 people (40,000 in
Knossos alone), the Minoans traded with the people of the Fertile Crescent.
Their palaces became the centers of economic activity and political power. The
palaces themselves were constructed with rooms of varying sizes and functions
and it seemed as if there were no apparent design (the Greeks later called them
labyrinths). Although the Minoans were remarkable for their trade networks,
architecture and the arts, their civilization eventually declined. Although
historians have not agreed on an exact cause, it has been suggested that a large
earthquake on the island of Thera may have created a tidal wave that engulfed
the island of Crete. Whatever the cause of their decline, Minoan society was
transformed by invaders from the Greek mainland.
How the Greeks settled on the Greek mainland is significant
for their future development. Greece is a mountainous country and full of
valleys. Greece is also nearly surrounded by water. Hopefully the geographical
differences between Greek civilization and that of Sumer or Egypt are apparent
to you. Because of their geography, the Greeks were encouraged to settle the
land in independent political communities. These communities would soon come to
be known as city-states. Each city state or polis had its own political
organization and thus was truly independent. The largest and most powerful of
all the city-states in the period 1600-1100 was that of Mycenae and this period
of time has come to be called the Mycenaen Age.
By the 16th century, MYCENAE was an extremely wealthy,
prosperous and powerful state. Archeological discoveries of the area have
uncovered swords, weapons and the remains of well-fortified city walls showing
that this city-state was indeed a community of warriors. Each city-state in the
Mycenaean period was independent and under the rule of its own king. The only
time the city-states may have united was during the war with Troy in Asia Minor.
By 1300, the Greek mainland was under attack by ships from
Asia Minor and by 1100, Mycenae was completely destroyed. This invasion is known
as the Dorian Invasion – the Doric Greeks were supposedly tribes who had left
Greece at an earlier time and then returned by 1200 B.C. Following the Dorian
Invasion Greece fell into its own period of the Dark Ages. For the most part,
Greek culture began to go into decline – pottery became less elegant, burials
were less ornate and the building of large structures and public buildings came
to an abrupt halt. However, the invasion and subsequent Dark Age did not mark
the end of Greek civilization. Some technological skills survived and the Greek
language was preserved by those people who settled in areas unaffected by the
Dorian Invasion.
After 800 B.C. a new spirit of optimism and adventure began
to appear in Greece. This spirit became so intensified that historians have
called the period from 800-600 the Greek Renaissance. For instance, in
literature, this is the age of the great epic poets, poets who wrote of the
deeds of mortal men as well as of immortal gods. It is also the period of the
first Olympic games, held in 776 B.C.
The best though sometimes unreliable source of Greek
civilization in this period is HOMER, and in particular, two epic poems usually
attributed to him. We don't really know much about Homer. His place of birth is
doubtful although Smyrna, Rhodes, Colophon, Salamis, Chios, Argos and Athens
have all contended for the honor of having been his birthplace. His date of
birth has been assumed to be as far back as 1200 B.C. but, based on the style of
his two epic poems, 850-800 B.C. seems more likely. It has been said that Homer
was blind, but even that is a matter of conjecture. And lastly, we are not even
sure that Homer wrote those two classics of the western literary canon, the
Iliad and the Odyssey.
The confusion arises from the fact that the world of Homer
was a world of oral tradition and oral history. There is evidence to show that
Homer's epics were really ballads and were chanted and altered for centuries
until they were finally digested into the form we know today 540 B.C. by
Pisistratus, a man we shall meet again but in a very different context. We shall
assume, as generations before us have done, that Homer was the author of the
Iliad and the Odyssey.
In twenty-four books of dactylic hexameter verse, the Iliad
narrates the events of the last year of the Trojan War, and focuses on the
withdrawal of Achilles from the contest and the disastrous effects of this act
on the Greek campaign. The Trojan War was fought between Greek invaders and the
defenders of Troy, probably near the beginning of the 12th century B.C.
Archeological evidence gathered in our own century shows that the war did indeed
take place and was based on the struggle for control of important trade routes
across the Hellespont, which were dominated by the city of Troy (see map). About
this war there grew a body of myth that was recounted by Homer in the Iliad, the
Odyssey and a number of now-lost epics.
According to the more familiar versions of this complex
myth, the cause of the war was the episode of the golden apple which resulted in
the abduction by the Trojan prince Paris of Helen, the wife of Menelaus, king of
Sparta. Earlier, most of the rulers of Greece had been suitors for the Hand of
Helen and her father, Tyndareus, had made them swear to support the one chosen.
So, they joined Menelaus and prepared to move against Troy under the leadership
of Agamemnon, king of Mycenae.
After forcing Agamemnon to sacrifice his daughter Iphigenia
to insure fair weather, they set sail for Troy. In the tenth and final year of
the war with Troy, Achilles withdrew from the fight in an argument with
Agamemnon over possession of a female captive, however, grieved by the death of
his friend Patroclus, he rejoined the battle and killed the Trojan leader,
Hector.
That, in brief, is the action of the Iliad. The characters
we encounter are warriors through and through – not just warriors, but
aristocratic warriors who considered greatness in battle to be the highest
virtue a man could attain. This HEROIC OUTLOOK was composed of courage, bravery
and glory in battle and was necessary for a strong city-state in Greek
civilization. But these were not self-interested goals alone. Instead, the
warrior fought bravely in service to his city-state. We are not talking about
patriotism here. Virtue was what made man a good citizen, and good citizens made
a great city-state. We shall encounter virtue a great deal in conjunction with
the Athenian city-state.
The world of Homer is a world of war, conflict, life and
death. In fact, when I think of all the descriptions of war that I have managed
to read over the years, none have drawn so clear a picture or image as has
Homer. From Book 4 of the Iliad we experience the following:
At last the armies clashed at one strategic point, they
slammed their shields together, pike scraped pike with the grappling strength of
fighters armed in bronze and their round shields pounded, boss on welded boss,
and the sound of struggle roared and rocked the earth. Screams of men and cries
of triumph breaking in one breath, fighters killing, fighters killed, and the
ground streamed blood. Wildly as two winter torrents raging down from the
mountains, swirling into a valley, hurl their great waters together, flash
floods from the wellsprings plunging down in a gorge and miles away in the hills
a shepherd hears the thunder – so from the grinding armies broke the cries and
crash of war.
Antilochus was the first to kill a Trojan captain, tough on
the front lines, Thalysias' son Echepolus. Antilochus thrust first, speared the
horsehair helmet right at the ridge, and the bronze spearpoint lodged in the
man's forehead, smashing through his skull and the dark came whirling down
across his eyes – he toppled down like a tower in the rough assault. As he fell
the enormous Elephenor grabbed his feet, Chalcodon's son, lord of the
brave-hearted Abantes, dragged him out from under the spears, rushing madly to
strip his gear but his rush was short-lived. Just as he dragged that corpse the
brave Agenor spied his ribs, bared by his shield as he bent low – Agenor stabbed
with a bronze spear and loosed his limbs, his life spirit left him and over his
dead body now the savage work went on, Achaeans and Trojans mauling each other
there like wolves, leaping, hurtling into each other, man throttling man.
In the Homeric world of war, men do not have rights, but
only duties. By serving the city-state with their virtuous behavior, they are
also serving themselves. Indeed, there was nothing higher or more sublime in the
Homeric world than virtue. And Homer's epic poems served as the Bible of ancient
Greece right down to the time of Alexander the Great in the 4th century B.C. In
fact, an education in the classical world meant the rote memorization of Homer's
Iliad and Odyssey.
Homer's world is a closed and finite world. This is
completely unlike our own world which is a mechanical world, governed by
mathematics and fixed physical laws. Homer's world is a living world – the
earth, man, animals and plants are all endowed with personality, emotion and
wills of their own. Even the gods and goddesses were endowed with these
qualities. The gods themselves could appear at any time and at any place.
Although the gods had no permanent relations with the world of men and women,
they were interested in their welfare. They also intervened in the affairs of
life, as Homer's Iliad makes abundantly clear. In general, the gods were the
guides and councilors of mortal men and women. Still, the gods and goddesses
often deceived men by offering them delusion rather than reality.
For Homer, the world was not governed by caprice, whim or
chance – what governed the world was "Moira" (fate, fortune, destiny). Fate was
a system of regulations that control the unfolding of all life, all men and
women, all things of the natural world, and all gods and goddesses. Fate was not
only a system of regulations but a fundamental law that maintained the world. It
is Moira that gives men and women their place and function in Greek society.
That is, it is Moira that determines who shall be slave or master, peasant or
warrior, citizen or non-citizen, Greek or barbarian. It is Moira that fixed the
rhythm of human life – from childhood through youth to old age and finally
death, it was Fate that regulated the personal growth of the individual. Even
the gods had their destinies determined by Moira. From the Iliad, the goddess
Athena expounds on this principle of Fate to Telemachus when she says the gods
may help mortals but "Death is the law for all: the gods themselves/Cannot avert
it from the man they cherish when baneful Moira has pronounced his doom."
Given all this, it should be obvious that Greek religion
was polytheistic. Homer endowed his gods with a personality and the gods
differed from men only (1) in their physical perfection and (2) in their
immortality. In other words, gods and goddesses, like men and women, could be
good, bad honest, devious, jealous, vengeful, calm, sober, quick-witted or dim.
The gods assisted their favorite mortals and punished those who defied their
will. Most gods were common to all Greeks but each city-state also had their own
patron deity. Gods and goddesses were worshipped in public. But there were also
household gods – the gods of the hearth – specific to each family or clan. The
general acceptance of these gods is a sign of a specific culture that arose
during the Greek Renaissance, a culture we can identify as "Panhellenic."
The Athenian Origins of
Direct Democracy
One of the hallmarks of GREEK CIVILIZATION was the polis,
or city-state. The city-states were small, independent communities which were
male-dominated and bound together by race. What this means is that membership in
the polis was hereditary and could not be passed on to someone outside the
citizen family. The citizens of any given polis were an elite group of people –
slaves, peasants, women and resident aliens were not part of the body of
citizens.
Originally the polis referred to a defensible area to which
farmers of a particular area could retreat in the event of an attack. The
Acropolis in Athens is one such example. Over time, towns grew around these
defensible areas. The growth of these towns was unplanned and unlike the
city-states we encounter at Sumer, they were not placed for commercial
convenience near rivers or seas. In fact, the poleis were situated well inland
to avoid raids by sea. With time, the agora or marketplace began to appear
within the polis. The agora was not only a marketplace but the heart of Greek
intellectual life and discourse.
The scale of the polis was indeed small. When the
philosopher Aristotle (384-322 B.C.) came to discuss the origins of the polis in
his book POLITICS in the early 4th century B.C. he suggested that "it is
necessary for the citizens to be of such a number that they knew each other's
personal qualities and thus can elect their officials and judge their fellows in
a court of law sensibly." Before Aristotle, Plato fixed the number of citizens
in an ideal state at 5040 adult males. For Plato (c.427-c.347 B.C.), as it was
for Aristotle, the one true criteria of the size of the polis was that all the
citizens know one another. The issue at stake here is between public and private
worlds. The ancient Greeks did not really see two distinct worlds in the lives
of the citizenry. Instead, the public world was to be joined with the private
world.
The citizens in any given polis were related to one another
by blood and so family ties were very strong. As boys, they grew up together in
schools, and as men, they served side by side during times of war. They debated
one another in public assemblies – they elected one another as magistrates –
they cast their votes as jurors for or against their fellow citizens. In such a
society – the society of the polis – all citizens were intimately and directly
involved in politics, justice, military service, religious ceremonies,
intellectual discussion, athletics and artistic pursuits. To shirk one's
responsibilities was not only rare but reprehensible in the eyes of the Greek
citizen. Greek citizens did not have rights, but duties. A citizen who did not
fulfill his duties was socially disruptive. At the polis of Sparta, such a
citizen was called "an Inferior." At Athens, a citizen who held no official
position or who was not a habitual orator in the Assembly was branded as
idiotai.
Every polis was different from another. For example, some
poleis had different names for the months of the year. Although there were
similarities and differences between the city-states, they all made the effort
to preserve their own unique identity. What we call the ancient Greek world was
really hundreds of independent city-states or poleis. No one polis was a replica
of another. Those who lived within the confines of a city state considered
everyone else to be inferior. Furthermore, those people who did not speak Greek
were referred to as barbar, the root of our word barbarian.
Sparta
There were two city-states that were indicative of Greek
city-states as a whole: Sparta and Athens. At Sparta, located on the
Peloponnesus (see map), five Dorian villages combined to form the Spartan state.
In the 8th century, this state conquered all the other peoples of Laconia, one
of the most fertile plains in Greece. Although the Spartans extended their
territory, they did not extend their citizenship. The new subjects (perioikoi)
were residents of Lacedaemonia, but citizens remained limited to those native
born at Sparta.
From Lycurgus (no one knows who this man was or why his
name carried so much significance for the Spartans), we learn that boys left
home at the age of seven. They were organized into troops and played competitive
games until their 18th year, when they underwent four years of military
training. From the ages of 18 to 28 they lived together in barracks. At the age
of 30, they became citizens in their own right. Amongst themselves they were
called "Equals" – in the eyes of everyone else, they were Spartans. There was
state education for girls who lived at home but who were also organized into
troops. Boys and girls met together to learn basic studies as well as to dance,
sing and play musical instruments. Relations between the sexes was much more
free than anywhere else in the Greek world. However, after marriage (usually at
30 for men, 16 for women), the husband ate at the men's club until the age of 60
while his wife remained at home.
The Spartan state arranged for a basic equality in land
holding and provided the citizens with laborers, called helots (conquered people
such as the Messenians who became Spartan serfs). In other words, the economy
was based on the idea that slaves would labor to supply the Spartan armies with
food, drink and clothing. As a result, the slave population of Sparta was
enormous, thus necessitating the sort of militaristic state that Sparta indeed
became. The Spartan constitution allowed for two kings and was therefore a dual
monarchy. As the highest magistrates in the city-state, these kings decided
issues of war and peace.
The Spartan constitution was mixed, containing elements of
monarchy, oligarchy and democracy. The oligarchic element was represented by a
Council (gerousia) of elders consisting of twenty-eight men over the age of
sixty who were held office for life. The elders had important judicial functions
and were also consulted before any proposal was put before the Assembly of
Spartan citizens. The Assembly (apella) consisted of all male citizens over
thirty years of age. In theory, it was the Assembly who was the final authority
but in practice the real function of the Assembly was to ratify decisions
already decided upon by the elders and kings
For the Greeks, citizenship – that is, the active
participation of all citizens in politics – was considered to be the supreme
creative art. In essence, the city-state was synonymous with its citizenry. Like
a sculptor, the citizen molded a fully rounded society to his preconceived
notion of what that society ought to be.
The system developed by the Spartan state by the late 6th
century B.C. was deliberate and purposeful. It was created not just to keep the
ever-growing population of helots in check but rather to realize man's full
ideal within the society of the polis. The Spartan ideal was austere, severe and
limited according to our standards. But when political thinkers such as Plato
decided to create their own ideal society on paper, they turned to Sparta for
examples and not to Athens. I imagine the real reason for this is that the
Spartans created a world in both theory and practice, while the Athenians almost
always seemed lost in what might come to be. Although we may find the Spartan
world to be repressive or indeed oppressive, this is not the way the Spartans
saw it. After all, they had equality in education, training and opportunity.
They also enjoyed a large income as well as pride and glory.
Athens
While Sparta developed their control over the Peloponnesus,
the city-state of Athens controlled the area of the Attic Peninsula, to the east
and northeast of Sparta (see map). Athens was similar to other city-states of
the period of the Greek Renaissance with two important differences: (1) it was
larger both geographically and in terms of its population and (2) those people
it conquered were not reduced to servitude – this was the rule at Sparta. So,
Athens never faced the problem of trying to control a large population of angry
and sometimes violent subjects. This also explains why Sparta had to remain an
intensely militaristic state.
Around the year 600 B.C., and while Lycurgus was reforming
the legal system of the Spartan state, Athens faced a deepening political
crisis. Those farmers who supplied the city-state with food could not keep up
with demand because the Athenian population had grown too quickly. Farmers began
to trade their land to obtain food and quickly went bankrupt as they traded away
their last piece of land. The crisis was solved in 594 B.C. when the Athenians
gave control over to Solon (c.640-c.559 B.C.), a former high official. In his
role as archon, Solon cancelled all agricultural debts and announced that all
slaves were free. He also passed constitutional reforms that divided Athenian
subjects into four classes based on their annual agricultural production rather
than birth. Members of the three highest orders could hold public office.
Solon's system excluded all those people who did not own
any productive land – women, children, slaves, resident aliens, artisans and
merchants. However, with the constitutional reforms of Solon, men from newer and
less-established families could work their way up economically and achieve
positions of political leadership. Solon did not end the agricultural crisis in
Greece and so factional strife remained.
In 561, the former military leader Pisistratus (c.600-527
B.C.) appeared at Athens and seized the Acropolis and began to rule as a tyrant
in place of Solon. Down to 527, the year of his death, he rewarded dispossessed
peasants with land confiscated from wealthier families. He also encouraged trade
and industry and engaged in great public works programs. Temples were built and
religious centers improved. New religious festivals were also introduced by
Pisistratus, such as the one devoted to the god Dionysis, the god of fertility.
By the middle of the 6th century, the city had grown in
size and in wealth. Furthermore, the common people had become more sure of
themselves -- they had a high standard of living, more leisure time at their
disposal and were far-better informed than their ancestors had been. Since a
tyrant like Pisistratus wanted to give his power over to a more popular base of
support, it was during his reign that the average citizen obtained his political
experience. Furthermore, because men continued to qualify for office on the
basis of wealth, and since incomes were rising in the 6th century, there was a
greater number of citizens being included in the operation of the government.
Pisistratus was succeeded by his eldest son, Hippias, whose
rule was somewhat similar to that of his father. In 514 B.C., his brother
Hipparchus was murdered and Hippias became nervous and suspicious. Finally, one
of the noble clans exiled by the sons of Pisistratus, the Alemaeonids, won favor
with the oracle at Delphi and used its support to persuade Sparta to attack the
Athenian tyranny. Led by Cleomenes I, the Spartans marched into Athenian
territory in 510 B.C. Hippias was deposed and fled to Persia.
Cleomenes' friend Isagoras held the leading position in
Athens after the withdrawal of the Spartan troops, but he was not unopposed.
Cleisthenes, of the restored Alemaeonid clan was his chief rival. Isagoras tried
to restore a version of the pre-Solonian aristocratic state by purifying the
citizen lists
Cleisthenes took an unprecedented action by turning to the
people for political support and won with it a program of great popular appeal.
In 508 B.C., Cleisthenes instituted a new political organization whereby the
citizens would take a more forceful and more direct role in running the
city-state. He called this new political organization demokratia, or democracy –
rule by the entire body of citizens. He created a Council of Five Hundred which
planned the business of the public assemblies. All male citizens over the age of
thirty could serve for a term of one year on the Council and no one could serve
more than two terms in a lifetime. Such an organization was necessary, thought
Cleisthenes, so that every citizen would learn from direct political experience.
With such a personal interest in his democracy, Cleisthenes believed that there
would be no citizens to conspire and attempt to abolish the system.
Cleisthenes also divided all Athenians into ten tribes
(replacing the original four). The composition of each tribe guaranteed that no
region would dominate any of them. Because the tribes had common religious
activities and fought as regimental units, the new organization would also
increase devotion to the polis and diminish regional division.
Each tribe would send fifty men to serve on the Council of
Five Hundred (thus replacing Solon's Council of 400). Each set of fifty men
would serve as a presiding committee for a period of thirty-five days. The
Council convened the Assembly – an Assembly which, as of the year 450 B.C. –
consisted of approximately 21,000 citizens. Of this number, perhaps 12-15000
were absent as they were serving in the army, navy or were simply away from
Athens on business or otherwise. The Council scrutinized the qualifications of
officials and the allocation of funds. They looked after the construction of
docks and surveyed public buildings. They collected rent on public land and
oversaw the redistribution of confiscated property. Members of the Council were
also responsible for examining the horses of the cavalry, administering state
pensions and receiving foreign delegations. In other words, the Council was
responsible for the smooth running of the daily operations of the Athenian
city-state.
Membership on the Council was for one year but it was
possible to serve a second term. A minimum of 250 new members had to be chosen
every year and it has been suggested that 35-45% of all Athenian citizens had
experience on the Council. Serving on the Council of Five Hundred was a full
time job and those who did serve were paid a fee.
Every year 500 Council members and 550 Guards were chosen
by lot from the villages of the Athenian polis. These men were scrutinized by
the Council before they were chosen so that alternates were always available.
The rapid turnover in the Council ensured (1) that a large number of Athenians
held some political position in their lifetime and that (2) the Assembly would
contain a larger and more sophisticated membership. The Assembly contained all
those citizens who were not serving on the Council of 500 or who were not
serving as public officials. The Assembly had forty regular meetings per year –
there were four meetings in each 35 day period into which the Council's year was
divided. The first meeting discussed the corn supply, the qualifications of
officials, questions of defense and ostracisms. The second meeting was open to
any issue, while the third and fourth meetings were given over to debates on
religion and foreign and secular affairs. Special meetings or emergency sessions
could be called at any time.
Around 460 B.C., Pericles (c.490-429 B.C.) used the power
of the people in the law courts and the Assembly to break up the Council of Five
Hundred. Under Pericles, ATHENIAN DEMOCRACY came to mean the equality of justice
and the equality of opportunity. The equality of justice was secured by the jury
system, which ensured that slaves and resident aliens were represented through
their patrons. The equality of opportunity did not mean that every man has the
right to everything. What it did mean is that the criteria for choosing citizens
for office was merit and efficiency and not wealth. Whereas Solon had used the
criterion of birth for his officials and Cleisthenes had used wealth, Pericles
now used merit. This was the ideal for Pericles. What indeed happened in
practice was quite different. The Greek historian Thucydides (c.460-c.400 B.C.)
commented on the reality of democracy under Pericles when he wrote: "It was in
theory, a democracy but in fact it became the rule of the first Athenian." And
the historian Herodotus (c.485-425 B.C.) added that "nothing could be found
better than the one man, the best." This "one man, the best," was the aristoi,
the word from which we get the expression aristocracy. So, what began as Greek
democracy under Cleisthenes around 500 B.C., became an aristocracy under
Pericles by 430 B.C.
The Council of Five Hundred and the Assembly met often and
what they discussed focused on decidedly local issues. But they also discussed
what we could only call democratic theory – that is, they constantly debated
questions like what is the good life? and what is the best form of government?
But perhaps the most important of all were discussions and debates over the
issues of war. And this is important to grasp for the 5th century, the classical
age of Greece, is an age of near constant warfare. Between 490 and 474 B.C., the
Greeks fought the Persians and at the end of the century (431-404 B.C.), a war
between Sparta and Athens not only spelled the end of Athenian dominance, but
also the death of Athenian direct democracy.
Classical Greece,
500-323 BC
When we think of ancient Greece and the ancient Greeks, it
is usually the 5th century which commands our undivided attention. This is the
age of the great historians Herodotus and Thucydides, great dramatists like
Sophocles, Euripides and Aeschylus, and the brilliant philosopher Socrates. The
5th century is also regarded as the age when the Greeks embraced their brilliant
experiment in direct democracy. Amazing monuments to human achievement were
constructed in Athens and other Hellenic city-states. It is an age of human
discovery and achievement – an age which proudly bears the name classical.
The Persian Invasion of
Greece
However, the 5th century was also an age of war and
conflict. Between 490 and 479 B.C., Greece was invaded by the army and naval
fleet of the Persian Empire. By about 500 B.C. the Greek city states had lost
their kings (with the exception of Sparta) and had embraced a new form of
government through councils of citizens. Almost immediately, however, these
states were confronted by an invasion of the Persian Empire.
King Darius (548-486 B.C.) managed to build up the Persian
Empire and now controlled Asia Minor, including Greek poleis on the west coast.
In 499 B.C., some of the these poleis rebelled from the Persians (an episode
called the Ionian Revolt). The Athenians lent their support but the revolt
ultimately collapsed in 493 B.C. Darius proposed now to invade mainland Greece –
his prime target was Athens. Darius sent his fleet across the Aegean in 490 and
awaited news of victory.
The Persians landed at Marathon, a village just north of
Athens. Commanded by Militiades, the Greek forces totaled only 10,000 men – the
Persian force was perhaps 20-25,000 strong. The Greek forces charged and trapped
the Persians and won the battle. The remainder of the Persians attempted to
attack Athens but the Greek army rushed back and the Persians were forced to
return to Asia Minor. The victory at MARATHON was won by superior timing and
discipline.
Darius prepared a second invasion but died (486 B.C.)
before his plans could be carried out. The task was taken up by Xerxes
(c.519-465 B.C.) who prepared a huge force that would attack by land and sea. In
483 B.C., the Athenian statesman Themistocles (c.523-c.458 B.C.) persuaded his
fellow Athenians to build a navy of one hundred triremes. He also oversaw the
fortification of the harbor at Piraeus. Fearing destruction at the hands of the
Persians, in 480 B.C. thirty poleis formed an alliance. Athens, Sparta and
Corinth were the most powerful members.
In 480 B.C., Xerxes sent a force of 60,000 men and 600
ships to Greece. The Greeks made their stand at Thermopylae. Five thousand men
took up their positions to defend the pass at Thermopylae. The Greeks held the
pass but eventually a traitorous Greek led a Persian force through the hills to
the rear of the Greek forces, who were subsequently massacred. Meanwhile, the
Greek navy tried to hold off the Persian ships at Artemisium. The Athenians
eventually abandoned Athens ahead of the Persian army. The Persians marched
across the Attic peninsula and burned Athens. Themistocles then sent a false
message to Xerxes, telling him to strike at once. The Persians were taken in and
sent their navy into the narrow strait between Athens and the island of Salamis.
More than three hundred Greek ships rammed the Persians and heavily armed Greek
soldiers boarded the ships. The Greek victory at Salamis was a decisive one.
However, Persian forces remained in Greece. Their final expulsion came in 479
B.C. at the village of Plataea.
By 479 B.C., the Greek forces had all conquered the Persian
army and navy. After the Persian Wars, Athens emerged as the most dominant
political and economic force in the Greek world. The Athenian polis, buttressed
by the strength of its Council of Five Hundred and Assembly of citizens, managed
to gain control of a confederation of city-states which gradually became the
Athenian Empire.
The Athenians not only had a political leadership based on
the principles of direct democracy as set in motion by Cleisthenes (see Lecture
6), they also had wide trading and commercial interests in the Mediterranean
world. These trading interests spread throughout the area of the Aegean Sea
including Asia Minor, an area known as the Aegean Basin. Greek victories against
the Persians secured mainland Greece from further invasion. There was a great
sense of relief on the part of all Greeks that they had now conquered the
conquerors. But, there were some citizens who argued in the Assembly that a true
Greek victory would only follow from total defeat of the Persians, and this
meant taking the war to Persia itself. And this is precisely what would happen
in the 5th century.
Meanwhile, dozens of Greek city-states joined together to
form a permanent union for the war. Delegates met on the island of Delos in 478
B.C. The allies swore oaths of alliance which were to last until lumps of iron,
thrown into the sea, rose again. The Delian League policy was to be established
by an assembly of representatives but was to be administered by an admiral and
ten treasurers appointed by Athens. It fell upon the Athenian leader, Aristides
the Just, to assign an assessment of 460 talents per year, which member states
paid in cash or in the form of manned ships. Right from the start, the Delian
League was dominated by Athenian authority and leadership. The Delian League had
its precedents: the Spartan League, the Ionian League of 499-494 B.C. and the
League of 481-478 B.C. Eventually, the Greeks liberated the cities of Asia Minor
and by 450 B.C., the war with the Persians came to an end.
It was at this time that the power of Athens was being felt
throughout the Greek world. And as the power of Athens reached new limits, its
political influence began to be extended as well. The Athenians forced
city-states to join the Delian league against their will. They refused to allow
city-states to withdraw from the League. And other city-states they simply
refused entry into the League. Athens stationed garrisons in other city-states
to keep the peace and to make sure that Athens would receive their support, both
politically and in terms of paying tribute to the League. By 454 B.C., Athenian
domination of the Delian League was clear – the proof is that the League's
treasury was moved from the temple of Apollo on the island of Delos to the
temple of Athena at Athens. Payments to the Delian League now became payments to
the treasury of Athens.
The Age of Pericles
It was around this time, 450-430 B.C., that Athens enjoyed
its greatest period of success. The period itself was dominated by the figure of
Pericles and so the era has often been called the Age of Pericles. The Athenian
statesman, Pericles (c.490-429 B.C.), was born of a distinguished family, was
carefully educated, and rapidly rose to the highest power as leader of the
Athenian democracy. Although a member of the aristoi, Pericles offered many
benefits to the common people of Athens and as a result, he earned their total
support. Oddly enough, the benefits he conferred upon the common people had the
result of weakening the aristocracy, the social class from which he came. As the
historian Thucydides pointed out, "he controlled the masses, rather than letting
them control him."
Pericles was a man of forceful character. He was an
outstanding orator, something which, as we have already seen, was absolutely
necessary in the political world of the Athenian Assembly. He was also honest in
his control of Athenian financial affairs. Pericles first rose to political
prominence in the 450s. At this time, the Athenian leadership was convinced of
two things: (1) the continuation of the war with the Persians and (2)
maintaining cordial relationships with Sparta. The strategy of Pericles was the
exact opposite. In the Assembly he argued convincingly that the affair with
Persia was in the past. He decided to concentrate instead on Sparta, which he
saw as a direct threat to the vitality of the Athenian Empire. As would be
evident by the end of the century, Sparta was a major threat. The reason for
this is quite simple. On the one hand, Sparta chose to isolate itself from the
affairs of other Greek city-states. On the other hand, Spartan isolationism
appeared as a direct threat to Athens. Whether or not the threat was real, the
bottom line is that Sparta and Athens were destined to become enemies.
From the 450s onward, Pericles rebuilt the city of Athens,
a city ravaged by years of wars with the Persians. He used the public money from
the Delian League to build several masterpieces of 5th century Greek
architecture, the Parthenon and the Propylaea.. This, of course, outraged many
of his fellow citizens who attacked him in the Assembly on more than one
occasion. The common people, however, were quick to support Pericles for the
simple matter that he gave them jobs and an income. Under Pericles, Athens
became the city of Aeschylus, Socrates and Phidias, the man in charge of all
public buildings and statues.
At this time Pericles also embarked on the path of
aggressive imperialism. He put down rebellions and sent his Athenian armies to
colonize other areas of Asia Minor. And while he was doing this, he was also
trying to foster the intellectual improvement of the Athenian citizen by
encouraged music and drama. Industry and commerce flourished. In 452/1 B.C.,
Pericles introduced pay for jurors and magistrates so that no one could be
barred by poverty from service to the polis. Indeed, under Pericles, Athens was
rebuilt and the population greeted him as their hero. But, there were problems
on the not-too-distant horizon.
The Peloponnesian War
These problems came to a head during the Peloponnesian Wars
of 431-404 B.C. As we've already seen, Sparta feared Athenian power – they
believed that Athens had grown too quickly both in terms of population and
military power. And Athens, of course, feared the Spartans because of their
isolationist position. What we have then, is a cold war turned hot. The
Peloponnesian War was a catastrophe for Athens. The chief result of the War was
that the Athenian Empire was divided, the subject states of the Delian league
were liberated, direct democracy failed and Pericles was ostracized. The
Athenians also suffered a loss of nerve as their democracy gave way to the Reign
of the Thirty Tyrants. The major result, however, was that the destruction of
Athenian power made it possible for the Macedonian conquest of Greece (see
Lecture 9).
By mid-century there had been several clashes between
Athens and Sparta and their respective allies. In 446 B.C. a treaty of
non-aggression was signed that would be valid for thirty years (a form of
détente, if you will). The peace did not last. In 435 B.C., a quarrel developed
between Corinth, an ally of Sparta, and Corcyra. In 433, Corcyra appealed to
Athens to form an alliance. The Corinthians knew that such an alliance would
make war inevitable. The combined naval power of Athens and Corcyra was the
largest in Greece, and Sparta viewed such an alliance as a direct threat. The
same year, the Athenians demanded that the town of Potidaea should dismantle its
defensive walls and banish its magistrates, a demand which further infuriated
the Corinthians. Athens besieged the town. An assembly of the Peloponnesian
league met and the Corinthians managed to convince the Spartans that war with
Athens was the only solution.
Fighting began in 431 B.C. Sparta wanted to break Athenian
morale by attacking Attica annually, but the Athenians merely retreated behind
their fortifications until the Spartan forces retired. Pericles refused to send
the Athenian infantry to the field. Instead he relied on raids on the
Peloponnesus by sea. More damaging than any offensive by the Spartans was a
PLAGUE that raged in Athens in 430. And the following year, Pericles died.
Over the next few years Athens and Sparta suffered so many
losses that both sides were prepared to end the conflict. The Peace of Nicias
was signed in 421 B.C. Hostilities were renewed in 415 when the people of
Segesta (a city in Sicily) appealed to Athens for help. It was Alcibiades
(c.450-404 B.C.) who persuaded the Athenian Assembly to raise a large fleet and
sail to Sicily. But it was the Athenian campaign against Syracuse that
eventually brought disaster. In 413 the Athenian navy lost a crucial battle. As
they retreated they were cut off and destroyed. Thucydides reported that "few
out of many returned home."
The war dragged on for another eight years. Sparta sought
decisive help by gaining the assistance of Persia. In 405 a Spartan admiral
captured the Athenian fleet at Aegospotami, on the shores of the Hellespont. The
following year, beaten into submission, Athens gave up control of its empire and
had to demolish its defensive walls. By 404 B.C., Sparta had "liberated" Greece
and imposed on oligarchic regime (the Thirty Tyrants), that lasted until the
following year.
After the death of Pericles and the disorder of a century
of warfare, the Greek city-states and direct democracy went into decline. The
reason is that first one polis, then another, rose up, withdrew from the Delian
League and began to assume control of their own affairs, without falling under
the sphere of Athenian influence. Sparta assumed leadership of the city-states.
Then it was the turn of Thebes, then Corcyra, then Corinth, the Sparta again.
This fragmentation and political disorder left the door open for political power
to come from an entirely different area of Greece – Macedonia. Under Philip II,
Macedonia flourished through diplomacy and military aggression. Philip took
advantage of the general disorder on the Attic peninsula, and extended his
control into central Greece. His armies defeated a weakened Athens. In fact,
Philip gained control of all the important Greek city-states with the exception
of Sparta. Philip was murdered in 336 B.C. and was succeeded by his son,
Alexander III. Under Alexander, the Macedonian Empire grew to become the largest
empire in the ancient world – larger even than the Roman Empire at its height.
Alexander the Great invaded what remained of the Persian Empire and gained
control of Asia Minor. Most of Egypt fell under his armies. His armies marched
as far east as the Indus River on the western border of India before he died of
fever in 323 B.C. at the age of thirty-three (see Lecture 9).
Greek Culture in the
Classical Age
The period from 500-323 B.C. is the Classical or Hellenic
age of Greek civilization. The brilliance of the Classical Greek world rested on
a blend of the old and the new. From the past came a profound religious belief
in the just action of the gods and the attainment of virtue in the polis. Such a
history helped develop a specific Greek "mind" in which the importance of the
individual and a rationalistic spirit were paramount. The Classical Greek world
was, in essence, a skillful combination of these qualities.
Athens never united all Greece. However, its culture was
unchallenged. The trade routes from the Aegean brought men and their ideas from
everywhere to the great cultural center of Athens. Thanks to its economic
initiative, the Athenian polis was quite wealthy, and Pericles generously
distributed that wealth to the Athenian citizen in a variety of forms.
For instance, the Athenian polis sponsored the production
of dramas and required that wealthy citizens pay the expenses of production. At
the beginning of every year, dramatists submitted their plays to the archon, or
chief magistrate. Each comedian presented one play for review; those who wrote
tragedy had to submit a set of three plays, plus an afterpiece called a satyr
play. It was the archon who chose those dramas he considered best. The archon
allotted to each tragedian his actors, paid at state expense, and a producer
(choregus). On the appointed day the Athenian public would gather at the theatre
of Dionysus on the south slope of the Acropolis, paid their admission of two
obols, and witnessed a series of plays. Judges drawn by lot awarded prizes to
the poet (crown of ivy), the actor (an inscription on a state list in the agora)
and to the choregus (a triumphal tablet).
The Athenian dramatists were the first artists in Western
society to examine such basic questions as the rights of the individual, the
demands of society upon the individual and the nature of good and evil.
Conflict, the basic stuff of life, is the constant element in Athenian drama.
AESCHYLUS (525-456 B.C.), the first of the great Athenian
dramatists, was also the first to express the agony of the individual caught in
conflict. In his trilogy of plays, The Oresteia, he deals with the themes of
betrayal, murder and reconciliation. The first play, The Agamemnon, depicts
Agamemnon's return from the Trojan War and his murder by his wife, Clytemnestra,
and her lover. In the second play, The Libation Bearers, Orestes, the son of
Agamemnon and Clytemnestra, avenges his father's death by killing his mother and
her lover. The last play, The Eumenides, works out the atonement of Orestes. The
Furies, goddesses who avenged murder, demand Orestes' death. When the jury at
Orestes' trial casts six votes to condemn and six to acquit, Athena cast the
deciding vote in favor of mercy. Aeschylus used The Eumenides to urge reason and
justice to reconcile fundamental human conflicts. Like Solon, Aeschylus believed
that the world was governed by divine justice which could not be violated with
impunity. When men exhibited hubris (pride or arrogance), which led them to go
beyond moderation, they must be punished. Another common theme was that through
suffering came knowledge. To act in accordance with the divine order meant
caution and moderation.
SOPHOCLES (496-406 B.C.), the premier playwright of the
second generation, also dealt with personal and political matters. In his
Antigone he examined the relationship between the individual and the state by
exploring conflict between the ties of kinship and the demands of the polis.
Almost all of the plays of Sophocles stand for the precedence of divine law over
human defects. In other words, human beings should do the will of the gods, even
without fully understanding it, for the gods stand for justice and order.
However, whereas Aeschylus concentrated on religious
matters, Sophocles dealt with the perennial problem of well-meaning men
struggling, unwisely and vainly, against their own fate. The characters in the
tragedies of Sophocles resist all warnings and inescapably meet with disaster.
In Oedipus Rex, Oedipus is warned not to pursue the mystery of his birth but he
insists on searching for the truth about himself (that he unwittingly killed his
father and married his mother). Events do not turn out as Oedipus had planned --
the individual is incapable of affecting the universal laws of human existence.
EURIPIDES (c.480-406 B.C.), the last of the three great
Greek tragic dramatists, also explored the theme of personal conflict within the
polis and the depths of the individual. With Euripides drama enters a new, more
personal phase – the gods were far less important than human beings. Euripides
viewed the human soul as a place where opposing forces struggle, where strong
passions such as hatred and jealousy conflict with reason. The essence of
Euripides' tragedy is the flawed character – men and women who bring disaster on
themselves and their loved ones because their passions overwhelm their reason.
It is the rationalist spirit of 5th century Greek
philosophic thought that permeates the tragedies of Euripides. He subjected the
problems of human life to critical analysis and challenged Athenian conventions.
Aristophanes would criticize Euripides for introducing the art of reasoning into
drama
The Greeks of the classical age not only perfected the art
of drama, but of comedy as well. ARISTOPHANES (c.448-c.380 B.C.) was an ardent
lover of the city and a ruthless critic of cranks and quacks. He lampooned
eminent generals, at times depicting them as little more than morons. He
commented snidely on Pericles, and poked fun at Socrates and Euripides. Even at
the height of the Peloponnesian War, Aristophanes proclaimed that peace was
preferable to war. Like Aeschylus, Sophocles and Euripides, Aristophanes used
his art to dramatize his ideas on the right conduct of the citizen and the value
of the polis.
The experience of the Persian and Peloponnesian wars also
helped develop the beginnings of historical writing. It is in the classical age
then, that we meet the father of history, HERODOTUS (c.485-425 B.C.). Born at
Halicarnassus in Asia Minor, Herodotus traveled widely before settling in the
Athens, the intellectual center of the Greek world. In his book, The History,
Herodotus chronicled the rise of the Persian Empire, the origins of both Athens
and Sparta, and then described the laws and customs of the Egyptians. The scope
of The History is awesome. Lacking newspapers, any sort of communications, or
ease of travel, Herodotus wrote a history that covered all the major events of
the Ancient Near East, Egypt and Greece.
The outbreak of the Peloponnesian War prompted THUCYDIDES
(c.460-c.400 B.C.) to write a history of its course in the belief that it would
be the greatest war in Greek history. An Athenian politician and general,
Thucydides saw action in the war until he was exiled for a defeat. Exile gave
him the time and opportunity to question eye-witnesses about the details of
events and to visit the actual battlefields. Since he was an aristocrat – an
aristoi – he had access to the inner circles, the men who made the decisions.
Thucydides saw the Peloponnesian War as highly destructive to Greek character.
He noted that the old, the noble, and the simple fell before ambition and lust
for power. He firmly rejected any notion that the gods intervened in human
affairs. In his view, the fate of men and women was entirely in their own hands.
It has been said that the Greeks are the first ancient
society with which modern western society (since the Renaissance, that is) feels
some sort of affinity. The ancient Greeks were clearly a people who warred and
enslaved people. They often did not live up to their own ideals. However, their
achievements in the areas of art, architecture, poetry, tragedy, science,
mathematics, history, philosophy and government were of the highest order and
worthy of emulation by the Romans and others. Western thought begins with the
Greeks, who first defined man as an individual with the capacity to use his
reason. Rising above magic and superstition, by the end of the fifth century,
the Greeks had discovered the means to give rational order to nature and to
human society.
The Greeks also created the concept (if not quite the
reality) of political freedom. The state was conceived as a community of free
citizens who made laws in their own interest. As a direct democracy, for
example, the Athenian citizen discussed, debated and voted on issues that
affected him directly. The Greek discovery that man (the citizen) is capable of
governing himself was a profound one.
Underlying the Greek achievement was humanism. The Greeks
expressed a belief in the worth, significance, and dignity of the individual.
Man should develop his personality fully in the city-state, a development which
would, in turn, create a sound city-state as well. The pursuit of excellence --
arete -- was paramount. Such an aspiration required effort, discipline and
intelligence. Man was master of himself.
Greek Thought: Socrates,
Plato and Aristotle
The political and social upheaval caused by the Persian
Wars as well as continued strife between Athens and Sparta (see Lecture 7) had
at least one unintended consequence . In the 5th century, a flood of new ideas
poured into Athens. In general, these new ideas came as a result of an influx of
Ionian thinkers into the Attic peninsula. Athens had become the intellectual and
artistic center of the Greek world. Furthermore, by the mid-5th century, it had
become more common for advanced thinkers to reject traditional explanations of
the world of nature. As a result of the experience of a century of war,
religious beliefs declined. Gods and goddesses were no longer held in the same
regard as they had been a century earlier. I suppose we could generalize and say
that the Persian and Peloponnesian Wars taught that the actions of men and women
determine their own destiny, and not "Moira." Meanwhile, more traditional
notions of right and wrong were called into question, and all of this was
expressed in Hellenic tragedy and comedy.
The Greeks used their creative energies to explain
experience by recourse to history, tragedy, comedy, art and architecture. But
their creative energies were also used to "invent" philosophy, defined as "the
love of wisdom." In general, philosophy came into existence when the Greeks
discovered their dissatisfaction with supernatural and mythical explanations of
reality. Over time, Greek thinkers began to suspect that there was a rational or
logical order to the universe.
The Pre-Socratic
Philosophers
The PRE-SOCRATIC philosophers came from the city of Miletus
in the region of Ionia. Miletus was a prominent trading depot and its people had
direct contact with the ideas of the Near East. Around 600 B.C., Milesian
thinkers "discovered" speculation after asking a simple but profound question:
"what exists?" It was the Ionian natural philosopher, Thales of Miletus
(c.624-548 B.C.), who answered that everything in the universe was made of water
and resolves itself into water. What was so revolutionary about Thales was that
he omitted the gods from his account of the origins of nature. It is also
necessary to point out that Thales committed none of his views to writing.
Anaximander of Miletus (c.611-c.547 B.C.), another Milesian thinker, rejected
Thales, and argued instead that an indefinite substance -- the Boundless -- was
the source of all things. According to Anaximander, the cold and wet condensed
to form the earth while the hot and dry formed the moon, sun and stars. The heat
from the fire in the skies dried the earth and shrank the seas. It's a rather
fantastic scheme, but at least Anaximander sought natural explanations for the
origin of the natural world.
Thales and Anaximander were "matter" philosophers -- they
believed that everything had its origin in a material substance. Pythagoras of
Samos (c.580-507 B.C.) did not find that nature of things in material substances
but in mathematical relationships. The Pythagoreans, who lived in Greek cities
in southern Italy, discovered that the intervals in the musical scale could be
expressed mathematically and that this principle could be extended to the
universe. In other words, the universe contained an inherent mathematical order.
What we witness in the Pythagoreans is the emphasis on form rather than matter,
and here we move from sense perception to the logic of mathematics.
Parmenides of Elea (c.515-450 B.C.), also challenged the
fundamental views of the Ionian philosophers that all things emerged from one
substance. What Parmenides did was to apply logic to the arguments of the
Pythagoreans, thus setting the groundwork of formal logic. He argued that
reality is one, eternal and unchanging. We "know" reality not by the senses,
which are capable of deception, but through the human mind, not through
experience, but through reason. As we shall see, this concept shall become
central to the philosophic thought of Plato.
Perhaps the most important of all the Pre-Socratic
philosophers was Heraclitus of Ephesus (fl. 500 B.C.). Known as "the weeping
philosopher" because of his pessimistic view of human nature and "the dark one"
because of the mystical obscurity of his thought, Heraclitus wrote On Nature,
fragments of which we still possess. Whereas the Pythagoreans had emphasized
harmony, Heraclitus suggested that life was maintained by a tension of
opposites, fighting a continuous battle in which neither side could win a final
victory. Movement and the flux of change were unceasing for individuals, but the
structure of the cosmos constant. This law of individual flux within a permanent
universal framework was guaranteed by the Logos, an intelligent governing
principle materially embodied as fire, and identified with soul or life.
Fire is the primordial element out of which all else has
arisen -- change (becoming) is the first principle of the universe. Cratylus, a
follower of Heraclitus, once made the remark that "You cannot step twice into
the same river." The water will be different water the second time, and if we
call the river the same, it is because we see its reality in its form. The
logical conclusion of this is the opposite of flux, that is, a belief in an
absolute, unchanging reality of which the world of change and movement is only a
quasi-existing phantom, phenomenal, not real.
Democritus of Abdera (c.460-370 B.C.) argued that knowledge
was derived through sense perception -- the senses illustrate to us that change
does occur in nature. However, Democritus also retained Parmenides' confidence
in human reason. His universe consisted of empty space and an infinite number of
atoms (a-tomos, the "uncuttable"). Eternal and indivisible, these atoms moved in
the void of space. An atomic theory to the core, Democritus saw all matter
constructed of atoms which accounted for all change in the natural world.
What the Pre-Socratic thinkers from Thales to Democritus
had done was nothing less than amazing -- they had given to nature a rational
and non-mythical foundation. This new approach allowed a critical analysis of
theories, whereas mythical explanations relied on blind faith alone. Such a
spirit even found its way into medicine, where the Greek physician Hippocrates
of Cos (c.460-c.377 B.C.) was able to distinguish between magic and medicine.
Physicians observed ill patients, classified symptoms and then made predictions
about the course of a disease. For instance, of epilepsy, he wrote: "It is not,
in my opinion, any more divine or more scared than other diseases, but has a
natural cause, and its supposed divine origin is due to men's inexperience, and
to their wonder at its peculiar character."
The Sophists
Into such an atmosphere of change came the traveling
teachers, the Sophists. The Sophists were a motley bunch – some hailed from the
Athenian polis or other city-states, but the majority came from Ionia, in Asia
Minor. The Sophists were men whose responsibility it was to train and educate
the sons of Athenian citizens. There were no formal school as we know them
today. Instead, these were peripatetic schools, meaning that the instructor
would walk with students and talk with them – for a fee, of course. The Sophists
taught the skills (sophia) of rhetoric and oratory. Both of these arts were
essential for the education of the Athenian citizenry. After all, it was the
sons of the citizens who would eventually find themselves debating important
issues in the Assembly and the Council of Five Hundred. Rhetoric can be
described as the art of composition, while oratory was the art of public
speaking.
The Sophists abandoned science, philosophy, mathematics and
ethics. What they taught was the subtle art of persuasion. A Sophist was a
person who could argue eloquently – and could prove a position whether that
position was correct or incorrect. In other words, what mattered was persuasion
and not truth. The Sophists were also relativists. They believed that there was
no such thing as a universal or absolute truth, valid at all times. According to
Protagoras (c.485-c.411 B.C.), "Man is the measure of all things." Everything is
relative and there are no values because man, individual man, is the measure of
all things. Nothing is good or bad since everything depends on the individual.
Gorgias of Leontini (c.485-c.380 B.C.), who visited Athens in 427, was a
well-paid teacher of rhetoric and famous for his saying that a man could not
know anything. And if he could, he could not describe it and if he could
describe it, no one would understand him.
The Sophistic movement of the fifth century B.C. has been
the subject of much discussion and there is no single view about their
significance. Plato's treatment of the Sophists in his late dialogue, the
Sophist, is hardly flattering. He does not treat them as real seekers after
truth but as men whose only concern was making money and teaching their students
success in argument by whatever means. Aristotle said that a Sophist was "one
who made money by sham wisdom."
At their very best, the Sophists challenged the accepted
values of the fifth century. They wanted the freedom to sweep away old
conventions as a way of finding a better understanding of the universe, the gods
and man. The Sophists have been compared with the philosophes of the 18th
century Enlightenment who also used criticism and reason to wipe out anything
they deemed was contrary to human reason. Regardless of what we think of the
Sophists as a group or individually, they certainly did have the cumulative
effect of further degrading a mythical understanding of the universe and of man.
Socrates
From the ranks of the Sophists came SOCRATES (c.469-399
B.C.), perhaps the most noble and wisest Athenian to have ever lived. He was
born sometime in 469, we don't know for sure. What we do know is that his father
was Sophroniscus, a stone cutter, and his mother, Phaenarete, was a midwife.
Sophroniscus was a close friend of the son of Aristides the Just (c.550-468
B.C.), and the young Socrates was familiar with members of the circle of
Pericles. In his youth he fought as a hoplite at Potidaea (432-429), Delium
(424) and Amphipolis (422) during the Peloponnesian Wars. To be sure, his later
absorption in philosophy made him neglect his private affairs and he eventually
fell to a level of comparative poverty. He was perhaps more in love with the
study of philosophy than with his family -- that his wife Xanthippe was shrew is
a later tale. In Plato's dialogue, the Crito, we meet a Socrates concerned with
the future of his three sons. Just the same, his entire life was subordinated to
"the supreme art of philosophy." He was a good citizen but held political office
only once – he was elected to the Council of Five Hundred in 406 B.C. In Plato's
Apology, Socrates remarks that:
The true champion if justice, if he intends to survive even
for a short time, must necessarily confine himself to private life and leave
politics alone.
What we can be sure about Socrates was that he was
remarkable for living the life he preached. Taking no fees, Socrates started and
dominated an argument wherever the young and intelligent would listen, and
people asked his advice on matters of practical conduct and educational
problems.
Socrates was not an attractive man -- he was snub-nosed,
prematurely bald, and overweight. But, he was strong in body and the
intellectual master of every one with whom he came into contact. The Athenian
youth flocked to his side as he walked the paths of the agora. They clung to his
every word and gesture. He was not a Sophist himself, but a philosopher, a lover
of wisdom.
In 399 B.C., Socrates was charged with impiety by a jury of
five hundred of his fellow citizens. His most famous student, Plato, tells us,
that he was charged "as an evil-doer and curious person, searching into things
under the earth and above the heavens; and making the worse appear the better
cause, and teaching all this to others." He was convicted to death by a margin
of six votes. Oddly enough, the jury offered Socrates the chance to pay a small
fine for his impiety. He rejected it. He also rejected the pleas of Plato and
other students who had a boat waiting for him at Piraeus that would take him to
freedom. But Socrates refused to break the law. What kind of citizen would he be
if he refused to accept the judgment of the jury? No citizen at all. He spent
his last days with his friends before he drank the fatal dose of hemlock.
The charge made against Socrates -- disbelief in the
state's gods -- implied un-Athenian activities which would corrupt the young and
the state if preached publicly. Meletus, the citizen who brought the indictment,
sought precedents in the impiety trials of Pericles' friends. Although Socrates
was neither a heretic nor an agnostic, there was prejudice against him. He also
managed to provoke hostility. For instance, the Delphic oracle is said to have
told Chaerephon that no man was wiser than Socrates. During his trial Socrates
had the audacity to use this as a justification of his examination of the
conduct of all Athenians, claiming that in exposing their falsehoods, he had
proved the god right -- he at least knew that he knew nothing. Although this
episode smacks of Socrates' well-known irony, he clearly did believe that his
mission was divinely inspired.
Socrates has been described as a gadfly -- a first-class
pain. The reason why this charge is somewhat justified is that he challenged his
students to think for themselves – to use their minds to answer questions. He
did not reveal answers. He did not reveal truth. Many of his questions were, on
the surface, quite simple: what is courage? what is virtue? what is duty? But
what Socrates discovered, and what he taught his students to discover, was that
most people could not answer these fundamental questions to his satisfaction,
yet all of them claimed to be courageous, virtuous and dutiful. So, what
Socrates knew, was that he knew nothing, upon this sole fact lay the source of
his wisdom. Socrates was not necessarily an intelligent man – but he was a wise
man. And there is a difference between the two.
Plato
Socrates wrote nothing himself. What we know of him comes
from the writings of two of his closest friends, Xenophon and Plato. Although
Xenophon (c.430-c.354 B.C.) did write four short portraits of Socrates, it is
almost to Plato alone that we know anything of Socrates. PLATO (c.427-347 B.C.)
came from a family of aristoi, served in the Peloponnesian War, and was perhaps
Socrates' most famous student. He was twenty-eight years old when Socrates was
put to death. At the age of forty, Plato established a school at Athens for the
education of Athenian youth. The Academy, as it was called, remained in
existence from 387 B.C. to A.D. 529, when it was closed by Justinian, the
Byzantine emperor.
Our knowledge of Socrates comes to us from numerous
dialogues which Plato wrote after 399. In nearly every dialogue – and there are
more than thirty that we know about – Socrates is the main speaker. The style of
the Plato's dialogue is important – it is the Socratic style that he employs
throughout. A Socratic dialogue takes the form of question-answer,
question-answer, question-answer. It is a dialectical style as well. Socrates
would argue both sides of a question in order to arrive at a conclusion. Then
that conclusion is argued against another assumption and so on. Perhaps it is
not that difficult to understand why Socrates was considered a gadfly!
There is a reason why Socrates employed this style, as well
as why Plato recorded his experience with Socrates in the form of a dialogue.
Socrates taught Plato a great many things, but one of the things Plato more or
less discovered on his own was that mankind is born with knowledge. That is,
knowledge is present in the human mind at birth. It is not so much that we
"learn" things in our daily experience, but that we "recollect" them. In other
words, this knowledge is already there. This may explain why Socrates did not
give his students answers, but only questions. His job was not to teach truth
but to show his students how they could "pull" truth out of their own minds (it
is for this reason that Socrates often considered himself a midwife in the labor
of knowledge). And this is the point of the dialogues. For only in conversation,
only in dialogue, can truth and wisdom come to the surface.
Plato's greatest and most enduring work was his lengthy
dialogue, The Republic. This dialogue has often been regarded as Plato's
blueprint for a future society of perfection. I do not accept this opinion.
Instead, I would like to suggest that The Republic is not a blueprint for a
future society, but rather, is a dialogue which discusses the education
necessary to produce such a society. It is an education of a strange sort – he
called it paideia. Nearly impossible to translate into modern idiom, paideia
refers to the process whereby the physical, mental and spiritual development of
the individual is of paramount importance. It is the education of the total
individual.
The Republic discusses a number of topics including the
nature of justice, statesmanship, ethics and the nature of politics. It is in
The Republic that Plato suggests that democracy was little more than a "charming
form of government." And this he is writing less than one hundred years after
the brilliant age of Periclean democracy. So much for democracy. After all, it
was Athenian democracy that convicted Socrates. For Plato, the citizens are the
least desirable participants in government. Instead, a philosopher-king or
guardian should hold the reigns of power. An aristocracy if you will – an
aristocracy of the very best – the best of the aristoi.
Plato's Republic also embodies one of the clearest
expressions of his theory of knowledge. In The Republic, Plato asks what is
knowledge? what is illusion? what is reality? how do we know? what makes a
thing, a thing? what can we know? These are epistemological questions – that is,
they are questions about knowledge itself. He distinguishes between the reality
presented to us by our senses – sight, touch, taste, sound and smell – and the
essence or Form of that reality. In other words, reality is always changing –
knowledge of reality is individual, it is particular, it is knowledge only to
the individual knower, it is not universal.
Building upon the wisdom of Socrates and Parmenides, Plato
argued that reality is known only through the mind. There is a higher world,
independent of the world we may experience through our senses. Because the
senses may deceive us, it is necessary that this higher world exist, a world of
Ideas or Forms -- of what is unchanging, absolute and universal. In other words,
although there may be something from the phenomenal world which we consider
beautiful or good or just, Plato postulates that there is a higher unchanging
reality of the beautiful, goodness or justice. To live in accordance with these
universal standards is the good life -- to grasp the Forms is to grasp ultimate
truth.
The unphilosophical man – that is, all of us – is at the
mercy of sense impressions and unfortunately, our sense impressions oftentimes
fail us. Our senses deceive us. But because we trust our senses, we are like
prisoners in a cave – we mistake shadows on a wall for reality. This is the
central argument of Plato's ALLEGORY OF THE CAVE which appears in Book VII of
The Republic.
Plato realized that the Athenian state, and along with it,
Athenian direct democracy, had failed to realize its lofty ideals. Instead, the
citizens sent Socrates to his death and direct democracy had failed. The purpose
of The Republic was something of a warning to all Athenians that without respect
for law, leadership and a sound education for the young, their city would
continue to decay. Plato wanted to rescue Athens from degeneration by reviving
that sense of community that had at one time made the polis great. The only way
to do this, Plato argued, was to give control over to the Philosopher-Kings, men
who had philosophical knowledge, and to give little more than "noble lies" to
everyone else. The problem as Plato saw it was that power and wisdom had
traveled divergent paths -- his solution was to unite them in the guise of the
Philosopher-King.
Aristotle
Plato's most famous student was ARISTOTLE (384-322 B.C.).
His father was the personal physician to Philip of Macedon and Aristotle was,
for a time at least, the personal tutor of Alexander the Great. Aristotle styled
himself a biologist – he is said to have spent his honeymoon collecting
specimens at the seashore. He too was charged with impiety, but fled rather than
face the charges – I suppose that tells you something about Aristotle.
At the age of eighteen, Aristotle became the student at the
Academy of Plato (who was then sixty years of age). Aristotle also started his
own school, the Lyceum in 335 B.C. It too was closed by Justinian in A.D. 529.
Aristotle was a "polymath" – he knew a great deal about nearly everything. Very
little of Aristotle's writings remain extant. But his students recorded nearly
everything he discussed at the Lyceum. In fact, the books to which Aristotle's
name is attributed are really little more than student notebooks. This may
account for the fact that Aristotle's philosophy is one of the more difficult to
digest. Regardless, Aristotle lectured on astronomy, physics, logic, aesthetics,
music, drama, tragedy, poetry, zoology, ethics and politics. The one field in
which he did not excel was mathematics. Plato, on the other hand, was a master
of geometry.
As a scientist, Aristotle's epistemology is perhaps closer
to our own. For Aristotle did not agree with Plato that there is an essence or
Form or Absolute behind every object in the phenomenal world. I suppose you
could argue that Aristotle came from the Jack Webb school of epistemology –
"nothing but the facts, Mam." Or, as one historian has put it: "The point is,
that an elephant, when present, is noticed." In other words, whereas Plato
suggested that man was born with knowledge, Aristotle argued that knowledge
comes from experience. And there, in the space of just a few decades, we have
the essence of those two philosophical traditions which have occupied the
western intellectual tradition for the past 2500 years. Rationalism – knowledge
is a priori (comes before experience) and Empiricism – knowledge is a posteriori
(comes after experience).
It is almost fitting that one of Plato's greatest students
ought to have also been his greatest critics. Like Democritus, Aristotle had
confidence in sense perception. As a result, he had little patience with Plato's
higher world of the Forms. However, Aristotle argued that there were universal
principles but that they are derived from experience. He could not accept, as
had Plato, that there was a world of Forms beyond space and time. Aristotle
argued that that there were Forms and Absolutes, but that they resided in the
thing itself. From our experience with horses, for instance, we can deduce the
essence of "horseness." This universal, as it had been for Plato, was the true
object of human knowledge.
It perhaps goes without saying that the western
intellectual tradition, as well as the history of western philosophy, must begin
with an investigation of ancient Greek thought. From Thales and the matter
philosophers to the empiricism of Aristotle, the Greeks passed on to the west a
spirit of rational inquiry that is very much our own intellectual property. And
while we may never think of Plato or Aristotle as we carry on in our daily
lives, it was their inquiry into knowledge that has served as the foundation for
all subsequent inquiries. Indeed, many have argued with W. H. Auden that "had
Greek civilization never existed we would never have become fully conscious,
which is to say that we would never have become, for better or worse, fully
human."
From Polis to
Cosmopolis: Alexander the Great and the Hellenistic World, 323-30 B.C.
There is little doubt that the Peloponnesian War ultimately
signified the end of the city-state as a creative force which fulfilled the
lives of the citizenry (on the Peloponnesian War, see Lecture 7). Throughout the
5th and 4th centuries, the political history of the Greek world degenerated into
oligarchy. Athenian direct democracy became a spent force as Athens lost its
leadership in the Greek world after its defeat at the hands of the Spartans. But
Spartan domination did not last very long. Full of arrogance and pride, Sparta
found itself engaged in war after war. The three leading city-states of Athens,
Sparta and Thebes traded positions of influence and power, sometimes two states
joining against the other for protection.
Although Athens was rebuilding itself and Sparta had been
invaded by victorious Theban armies, the real center of Greek power in the first
half of the 4th century Greek world came from the Macedonian kingdom to the
north, an area to which the Attic Greeks regarded with disdain since that
kingdom was inhabited by barbaroi.
Philip of Macedon
In 359 B.C., PHILIP II of Macedon (383-336 B.C.) came to
the throne by a rather typical procedure – a round of family assassinations.
Philip was an energetic and ambitious man – if anything motivated him besides
greed, it was his awareness of just how divided and disordered the Greek world
had become. This disorder was a direct result of a century of warfare and in
particular, the Peloponnesian Wars. With this in mind, Philip set out to conquer
the Hellenic world. He accomplished this task by treachery, secrecy, speed and
dishonesty. He quieted his rivals, crushed rebellions and made secret treaties
which were broken almost as quickly as they were made.
In 338, Philip announced that he would marry Cleopatra, the
daughter of a wealthy Macedonian family. This is interesting since Philip was
already married to Olympias! Alexander was Philip's first born son and had the
claim to the throne. But Philip confined Olympias on the grounds that she had
committed adultery and encouraged rumors that Alexander was illegitimate. Philip
then arranged for a wedding feast – it turned out to be an intense affair.
Alexander entered the room and sat next Philip and said: "when my mother gets
married again I'll invite you to her wedding." Such a remark did nothing to
improve anyone's temper.
Throughout the evening enormous quantities of wine were
drunk. At last, Attalus, the bride's uncle arose, a bit unsteady, and proposed a
toast. He called upon the gods that there might be born a legitimate successor
to the Macedonia Kingdom. Infuriated, Alexander jumped to his feet and said:
"are you calling me a bastard?" He then threw his cup of wine in the face of
Attalus, who then did the same to Alexander. Philip stood, very drunk, and
lunged forward with his sword drawn. His target was not Attalus but Alexander.
However, Philip missed, tripped over a foot stool, and fell face first on the
floor. Alexander looked about him – looked at his father's worthless favorites –
and said: "That, gentlemen, is the man who's been preparing to cross from Europe
into Asia, and he can't even make it from one couch to the next!" Here was the
moment of crisis. Who would succeed Philip?
By this time, Olympias had clearly sided with her son
Alexander. The night before her wedding to Philip, Olympias had a dream that her
child would be a divine king. And she had always taught him that he was not
merely the next in line, but from his youth, she told him to think he was a king
in his own right. There is little doubt that Alexander and Olympias wished
Philip out of the way. And that opportunity appeared in 336 B.C.
Philip arranged a massive festival to honor the marriage of
Alexander's sister. With perfect timing, Philip's young wife Cleopatra had just
given birth to a son. Meanwhile, Alexander had been all but isolated from his
father's court. On the second day of the festivities, Philip was murdered by
member of his own bodyguard. As the king entered the arena, a man drew a short,
broad-bladed Celtic sword and thrust it into Philip's chest. Philip died
immediately. Philip's murderer was Pausanias, who was also Philip's lover.
Philip jilted Pausanias the year before for another young boy so the cause of
Philip's murder was not really political, but sexual. However, evidence exists
that connects Pausanias to Olympias, who promised him rewards and high honors if
he killed Philip.
But Pausanias knew too much – although Olympias promised
him an escape after he had done the dirty deed, the fact is that Olympias had to
get rid of Pausanias as well. He was killed minutes after Philip was murdered by
three soldiers loyal to Alexander and his mother. This is a bit of intrigue
which, as we shall see, shall be repeated throughout the history of the Roman
and Byzantine empires.
Alexander the Great
The throne fell to Philip's son, Alexander III (356-323
B.C.) or, as he is better known, ALEXANDER THE GREAT. When Alexander gained the
throne he had just reached his 20th birthday. Within fifteen months he stamped
out rebellions, marched into various Greek cities demanding submission, sent his
armies as far north as the Danube River, and destroyed the city of Thebes. In
334, and with 37,000 men under his command, he marched into Asia, still
conquering lands for his empire. He added new lands to old and carefully
consolidated his conquests by founding Greek cities abroad. Of the seventy
cities he founded, more than twenty bear his name. By 327, Alexander's armies
had moved as far east as India (see map). However, his troops were exhausted and
could go no further. We can only wonder how much more territory Alexander would
have added to the Empire had he had a fresh supply of troops.
Regardless, his illustrious career as leader and military
strategist came to an end in 323 B.C., when he died from fever after a
particularly wild party. He was 33 years old. Alexander has been portrayed as an
idealistic visionary and as an arrogant and ruthless conqueror. Well, how did he
view himself? He sought to imitate Achilles, the hero of Homer's Iliad. He
claimed to be descended from Hercules, a Greek hero worshipped as a god. In the
Egyptian fashion, he called himself pharaoh. After victories against the
Persians, he adopted features of their rule. He called himself the Great King.
He urged his followers to bow down before him, in Persian fashion. He also
married Roxane, a Persian captive, and arranged for more than 10,000 of his
soldiers to do the same. He wore Persian clothes and used Persians as
administrators. By doing this, Alexander was trying to fuse the cultures of East
and West, of Asia Minor and Greece. This fusion, and all that it came to
represent, is what historians mean by the expression Hellenization.
He was loved by his loyal soldiers but his fellow
Macedonians often objected to him. More than one assassination attempt was made
on his life. The cultural legacy of Alexander was that Hellenic art, drama,
philosophy, architecture, literature, and language was diffused throughout the
Near East. The cities he founded became the spring boards for the diffusion of
Hellenistic culture. Of the 60 to 70,000 mercenaries he summoned from Greece,
nearly 40,000 remained to inhabit these cities. His vision of empire no doubt
appealed to the Romans, a people who would eventually inherit Alexander's Empire
and, as we shall see, quite a bit more. However, when Alexander died in 323
B.C., the classical age of Greece came to an abrupt end. Something very
different was about to emerge.
From Polis to Cosmopolis
The immediate cause for the collapse of Classical Greece
was the experience of a century of warfare. The city-state could no longer
supply a tolerable way of life for its citizens. Intellectuals began to turn
away from the principles of direct democracy and embrace the idea of the
monarchy. For instance, Plato gave up on democracy in despair and insisted on a
Philosopher-King, something which he argued in The Republic. After all, the same
democracy that had made Athens so great in the mid-5th century, had also killed
his friend and teacher Socrates. Furthermore, the transition from the Greece of
Pericles to that of Alexander the Great, involves something more than just the
experience of warfare.
On a spiritual level, the 4th century witnessed a permanent
change in the attitudes of all Greeks. What resulted was a new attitude toward
life and its expectations – a new world view. In the classical world of the
polis, public and private lives were fused. Duty to the city-state was in itself
virtuous. But in the Hellenistic world, public and private lives were made
separate, and the individual's only duty was to himself. In art, sculpture,
architecture, or philosophy or wherever we choose to look, we see more attention
paid to individualism and introspection. Universal principles of truth – Plato's
Ideas and Forms – were rejected in favor of individual traits. By the 4th
century, Greek citizens became more interested in their private affairs rather
than in the affairs of the polis. For example, in the 5th century, we will find
comedies in which the polis is criticized, parodied and lampooned. But in the
4th century, the subject matter has changed and has turned to private and
domestic life. In other words, whereas 5th century comedies focused on the
relationship between the citizen and city-state, 4th century comedies made jokes
about cooks, the price of fish, and incompetent doctors.
But, the question remains – how do we account for the
DECLINE OF THE POLIS? Why was this brilliant experiment in direct democracy
destined for failure?
In general, the democracy of the city-state was made for
the amateur and not the professional. The ideal of the polis was that every
individual was to take a direct role in political, economic, spiritual and
social affairs. But perhaps this was just too much responsibility to place on
the shoulders of the citizens. For instance, we have Socrates, the most noble
Athenian. He spent his entire life trying to fathom the mysteries of life: what
is virtue? what is justice? what is beauty? what is the best form of government?
what is the good life? He didn't know the answer to these questions but he tried
to find out by asking as many people as many questions as possible. What
Socrates found was that no Athenian citizen could give him a definition of any
moral or intellectual virtue that would survive ten minutes of his questioning.
The effect of such a discovery on the part of the young men of Athens was
profound. Faith in the polis was shattered for how could the polis train its
citizens to be virtuous if no one knew what it meant to be virtuous.
With this story of Socrates in mind, we turn to his most
brilliant student, Plato. His Republic, his dialogue on the education required
to fashion a new state, rejects both the polis and the idea of direct democracy.
Just the fact that Plato was thinking in terms of an ideal state should tell you
something – people don't think of ideal societies when times are good.
Obviously, something was very wrong. Plato's solution was that the training of
citizens in virtue should be left to those who understand the universal meaning
of virtue, and in Plato's mind, that meant those people who had emerged from the
cave of illusion and who had seen the light of reality, that is, a
Philosopher-King. This is indeed a far cry from the ideal of direct democracy
and the city-state as embraced by a Solon, a Cleisthenes or a Pericles.
The history of the Greek world following the death of
Alexander is one of warfare and strife as his generals struggled for control of
Alexander's empire. By 275 B.C., Alexander's world had been divided into the
three kingdoms of Macedonia (Antigonids), Western Asia (Seleucids) and Egypt
(Ptolemaic). The kingdom of Pergamum (southern Asia Minor) was soon added as the
fourth Hellenistic monarchy.
Hellenistic Greece was a predominately urban culture. The
cities founded by Alexander were centers of government and trade as well as
culture. These were large cities by ancient standards. For instance, Alexandria
in Egypt contained perhaps 500,000 people. The Greeks brought their temples,
their theatres and schools to other cities, thus exporting their culture and
Greek culture became a way of life. The library at Alexandria is said to have
contained some half a million volumes. The upper classes began to copy the Greek
spirit. They sent their children to Greek schools and the Greek language (Koine)
became a common, almost international language, in the same way that Latin was
for Europe for fifteen centuries, or French in the 19th century.
What the breakdown of Alexander's empire had accomplished
was nothing less than the Hellenization of the Mediterranean world. Cultures
once foreign to the Hellenic world now became more Greek-like – they were
Hellenized. One of the most important developments in association with this
process of Hellenization, was the shift from the world of the polis to the new
world of the cosmopolis. Such a shift was decisive in creating the Hellenistic
world as a world of conflicting identities, and when identities are challenged
or changed, intense internal conflicts are the result.
We can identify this sense of conflict in the transition
from Classical to Hellenistic philosophy. Classical Greek philosophy, the
philosophy of the Sophists and of Socrates in the 5th century, was concerned
with the citizen's intimate relationship with the polis or city-state. You can
see this clearly in the philosophy of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle. Big
questions such as what is the good life, what is the best form of government and
what is virtue loomed large in their thinking. When we enter the world of the
Hellenistic philosopher we encounter something very different. We must ask why?
The world of the polis had clearly given way to the world
of the cosmopolis. And with that change from the smallness of the city-state to
the immensity of the world-city, there were corresponding changes in the world
view. The city-state was no longer run by citizens, citizens whose private and
public duties were identical. In the world-state, bureaucrats and officials took
over the duties formerly given over to citizens. Citizens lost their sense of
importance as they became subjects under the control of vast bureaucratic
kingdoms. From the face-to-face contact of the Athenian public Assembly, the
people now became little more than numbers. As a result, they lost their
identity.
Hellenistic Philosophy
This tendency was reflected in philosophy, which turned to
concern itself with the possibilities of survival in a world that had become
much larger, less personal, and more complex. Philosophy then, became less the
love of wisdom, than it did a therapy used to cope with a strange, fragmented
world of disorder and isolation. And as a result of this, there were two schools
of thought – two therapies – which made their appearance during the Hellenistic
Age. Both were therapies addressing themselves to an individualistic age. People
seemed less concerned about the nature of politics and their role in it. They
became more concerned about their own lives and were searching for some kind of
personal guidance. And all this was reflected in Hellenistic thought as THERAPY.
It was EPICURUS (341-270) who founded the school of
Epicureanism at the end of the fourth century. Epicurus taught the value of
passivity and withdrawal from public life altogether. Individual happiness could
be found anywhere, and just just within the confines of the polis. What politics
did was to deprive the citizen of his self-sufficiency and his freedom to choose
and to act. Wealth and power did little more than provoke anxiety. Epicurus
argued that people should strive for inner peace and tranquility and live
pleasurable lives while avoiding mental and physical pain. The wise person
should withdraw from the world and study philosophy and enjoy the companionship
of a few close friends.
Epicurus suggested a theory of nature that had no place for
the activity of gods. That the gods could inflict suffering after death was the
major cause of human anxiety. Epicurus adopted the atomic theory of Democritus,
who taught that in a universe of colliding atoms there could be no room for
divine activity (see Lecture 8). While he perhaps accepted the existence of
gods, he said it was pointless to worry about them.
People could achieve happiness when their bodies were free
from pain and their minds "released from worry and fear." Of course, Epicurus
did not mean that the individual ought to indulge in senseless hedonism.
Together with Aristotle, the motto of Epicurus could have been something like,
"nothing to excess." By opening his philosophy to all men and women, as well as
slaves, Epicurus created a therapy keenly adapted to the Hellenistic world of
cosmopolitan kingdoms.
The school of Stoicism was founded by Zeno (c.336-c.265
B.C.) in the late 4th century. Zeno was born at Citium, a small Phoenician-Greek
city on Cyprus. His father, Mnaseas, was a merchant and, according to Diogenes
Laertius (fl. 2nd century A.D.), he brought back many Socratic books to Zeno
when he was still a boy. At the age of twenty-two Zeno went to Athens and in 300
he started his school, first called the Zenonians and later called the Stoics
because he gave his lectures in the Stoa Poikile, or Painted Colonnade, where he
soon became a familiar part of Athenian intellectual life. His followers were
known as the Stoics or "Colonnaders." Diogenes Laertius relates that Zeno used
to set out his arguments while walking back and forth in the Painted Stoa which
was also named for Peisianax, but [called] "Painted" because of the painting by
Polygnotus. He wanted to make sure that his space was unobstructed by
bystanders; for under the Thirty Tyrants 1400 citizens had been slaughtered in
it. Still, people came to listen to him and for this reason they were called
Stoics; and his followers were given the same name, although they had previously
been called Zenonians, as Epicurus also says in his letters.
Zeno taught that a single, divine plan governed the
universe. To find happiness, one must act in harmony with this divine plan. By
cultivating a sense of duty and self-discipline, one can learn to accept their
fate – they will then achieve some kind of inner peace, freedom and tranquility.
The Stoics believed that all people belong to the single family of mankind and
so one should not withdraw from the world, but try to make something of the
world. The Stoics believed that the universe contained a principle of order,
called the Divine Fire, God or Divine Reason (Logos). This was the principle
that formed the basis for reality -- it permeated all things. Because men was
part of the universe, he too shared in the Logos. Since reason was common to
all, human beings were essentially brothers -- it made no difference whether one
were Greek, barbarian, free man or slave since all mankind were fellow citizens
of a world community. It was the Stoics who took the essentials of Socratic
thought -- a morality of self-mastery based on knowledge -- and applied it
beyond the Athenian polis to the world community.
By teaching that there was a single divine plan (Logos),
and that the world constituted a single society, it was Zeno who gave perfect
expression to the cosmopolitan nature of the post-Alexandrine world. Stoicism,
then, offered an answer to the problem of alienation and fragmentation created
by the decline of the polis. Surrounded by a world of uncertainty, Stoicism
promised individual happiness.
Both Epicureanism and Stoicism are therapies which
reflected the change in man's social and political life during the Hellenistic
Age. On the one hand, both therapies suggest a disenchantment with the overtly
political world of a Pericles or Thucydides, Athenian or Spartan. So, they can
be seen as direct reactions to the philosophy of both Plato and Aristotle. On
the other hand, the Stoics and Epicureans also reflect profound social changes
within Greece itself. Greek society had become more complex and more urban as a
result of Alexander's conquests. Politics fell into the hands of the wealthy few
and the citizens were left with nothing. And Hellenistic politics became little
more than an affair of aristocrats and their bureaucratic lackeys and experts.
Much of this is similar to modern times. Our government has
grown too complex and too large. Despite our democratic institutions, our
society is ordered and controlled by wealthy elites and bureaucrats, many of
whom we cannot even identify because their existence is not individual but
corporate. Modern society has become and remains impersonal, bureaucratic and
authoritarian. We believe we are in control. In reality, we are still prisoners
in Plato's cave where our illusions are fed to us by digital technology.
Hellenistic philosophers questioned such an order and in
general, turned to the inner harmony of the individual – a form of therapy with
which to deal with an increasingly cold and impersonal world. This is an ironic
situation. A culture congratulates itself that it has been able to progress from
simplicity to complexity. But with complexity – improvement? progress? – the
control of one's life seems to fall away. We are not in control since control is
in the hands of unidentifiable entities.
Given this, Hellenistic Greeks turned to personal
philosophies – therapies – for comfort and, if you will, salvation. What do we
turn to? Do we turn inward? No! the majority of us "find ourselves" reflected in
things external to us. We become members of "the club," losing our own identity
in collective identities. We are asked to say, "don't worry, be happy." In the
Hellenistic world, Stoicism became the point of view and therapy of choice for
individuals who were still trying to bring order out of the chaos of Hellenistic
life. The Epicureans appealed to those people who had resigned themselves to all
the chaos and instead turned to the quest for pleasure and the avoidance of
pain.
However, Stoicism and Epicureanism were not the only two
therapies available for those who needed them. The SKEPTICS simply denied that
there was anything close to true knowledge. According to the 4th century Skeptic
Cratylus, since everything is changing, one cannot step once into the same
river, because both that river and oneself are changing. Cratylus took his brand
of skepticism to an alarming degree, arguing eventually that communication was
impossible because since the speaker, listener and words were changing, whatever
meaning might have been intended by the words would be altered by the time they
were heard. He is therefore supposed to have refused to discuss anything and
only to have wiggled his finger when someone spoke, to indicate that he had
heard something but that it would be pointless to reply, since everything was
changing.
Whereas the Epicureans withdrew from the evils of the
world, and the Stoics sought happiness by working in harmony with the Logos, the
Skeptics held that one could achieve some kind of spiritual equilibrium only by
accepting that none of the beliefs by which people lived were true or could
bring happiness. Speculative thought did not bring happiness either. For the
most part, the Skeptics were suspicious of ideas and maintained no great love
for intellectuals.
The Cynics rejected all material possessions and luxuries
and lived simple lives totally divorced from the hustle and bustle of the
Hellenistic world-city. The most famous of the Cynics was Diogenes the Dog
(412-323 B.C.). Diogenes lived in a bath tub. He carried a lantern in daylight,
proclaiming to all that he was looking for a "virtuous man." It is said that one
day Alexander the Great approached Diogenes, who was near death, and asked if
there was anything that he could do for him. Diogenes is said to have replied,
"would you mind moving – you are blocking the sun." Plato described Diogenes as
"Socrates gone mad." He called himself "citizen of the world and when asked what
the finest thing in the world might be, replied "freedom of speech." Diogenes
was a serious teacher who, disillusioned with a corrupt society and hostile
world, protested by advocating happiness as self-mastery of an inner spiritual
freedom from all wants except the barest minimum. In his crusade against the
corrupting influence of money, power, fame, pleasure and luxury, Diogenes
extolled the painful effort involved in the mental and physical training
required for self-sufficiency.
And finally, there were the Neo-Platonists who combined
Plato's ideas with the ancient religions that flourished in Asia Minor. The
Neo-Platonists used the Allegory of the Cave as their point of departure. They
took the Allegory and "socialized" it by arguing mankind can overcome this
material world by mastering the scared lore and special knowledge contained in
the mystery cults.
From Epicurean to Stoic and from Skeptic and Cynic to
Neo-Platonist, none of these therapies provided any sort of relief for the
ordinary man and woman. After all, these therapies were specifically "upper
class" philosophies, intended for citizens feeling the burdens of the cosmopolis
upon their social, political and economic life. In other words, one studied with
Zeno or Diogenes or they read the books of Epicurus or the Neo-Platonists. The
common person required something more concrete, more practical and less
demanding as well as more helpful than the philosophic therapists could offer.
They found what they wanted in the mystery cults, cults which could explain
their suffering in less complex and more down-to-earth terms.
The most popular cults were those associated with a
mother-goddess such as Ishtar (Sumer) or Isis (Egypt) or those that taught the
coming of a savior such as Osiris and Mithra. The savior would come to deliver
man from the forces of darkness which had threatened to consume him. The
mother-goddess cult taught that one should take comfort in the love that the
mother figure offered and await with patience for one's death when one would be
reunited with the mother-goddess. The savior cult invited one to worship a
hero-god who would then offer protection from evil. Many of these cults offered
beliefs in the resurrection of the body after death. Hopefully you can see that
these cults were an amalgamation of Hebrew monotheism and Egyptian and Sumerian
polytheism. We should also not forget that although faith in the pantheon of
gods and goddesses declined during the Hellenic or Classical age of Greece, its
decline was felt most strongly amongst the citizenry and not the common people,
who continued to maintain their traditional beliefs of gods and goddesses of the
hearth.
The mystery cults usually enforced certain dietary rules
and also required participation in various rites. The cults were not exclusive
and therefore anyone could join at will. The mystery cults afforded a community
of feeling and aspiration that took the place of the now defunct polis. When it
first appeared in the Roman world, Christianity was identified by the Romans as
merely another mystery cult. Only gradually did it dawn on the Romans that they
were facing a completely new religious phenomenon. And I mention this now in
order to suggest that the mystery cults would contribute to the overall
Christianization of the Roman Empire. In other words, when Christianity did make
its appearance, the mystery cults had already prepared the groundwork for its
acceptance by the Roman people.
There was one distinct culture that knew the Greeks most
intimately – the Romans. The Romans had built a stable political and social
order in central Italy while the Greeks were witnessing the decline of the
city-state during the Hellenistic Age. The Romans resembled the Greeks in many
respects with one important difference. The Romans successfully created the kind
of cosmopolitan world order – the Empire – of which the Greeks had only dreamed.
Grace Notes is a ministry of
Austin Bible Church, Austin, Texas
http://www.austinbiblechurch.com
E-Mail:
wdoud@gracenotes.info
Web:
http://www.gracenotes.info